Thursday 31 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of A Passive Verbal Group

Matthiessen (1995: 739):
Another more complex example is the one shown in Figure 7-38, mentioned earlier.

 Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this misconstrues and misrepresents the univariate structure of the verbal group. Because there are only five features selected — future, past, future, past, passive — there are only five elements of univariate structure, not six:

will have been going to have been tested

α future  β past      γ future        δ past     ε passive

Tuesday 29 August 2023

Naming Tense Selections

Matthiessen (1995: 735):
The most convenient way of naming these tense selections is to start with the last selection and work towards the first. This indicates the context in which a given tense selection has been made; for example, primary: past, secondary: future, tertiary: past — was going to have walked — is called past-in-future-in-present. The following example (taken from Halliday, 1976; 1981) is present-in-future-in-past-in-future:

 Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, this is merely a typo that should read 'past'. The univariate structure is:

was going to have walked

α past    β future              γ past

past in future in past


[2] To be clear, this misconstrues and misrepresents the univariate structure of the verbal group. Because there are only five features selected — future, past, future, present, passive — there are only five elements of univariate structure, not six:

will have been going to be being tested

α future β past γ future δ present ε passive

passive: present in future in past in future.

Sunday 27 August 2023

The Realisation Of Secondary Tense

Matthiessen (1995: 734):
Secondary tenses are realised by tense auxiliaries followed by the particular verb form they govern:
Secondary past is realised by the tense auxiliary have followed by the past participial form (v-en), as in have eaten; have walked; have been eating; have been walking.

Secondary present is realised by the tense auxiliary be followed by the present participial form (v-ing), as in be eating; be walking; be being eaten.

Secondary future is realised by the tense auxiliary be going + a to infinitival verb form (to v), as in be going to eat, be going to have eaten, be going to be eating. (We can also include forms such as be about to for immediate future and would as a special form for future-in-past, as in He would later regret his rash decision.)


Blogger Comments:

This is misleading because it misrepresents words as the realisation of secondary tense in univariate structure. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 398-9):

… the elements of the logical structure are not the individual words but certain rather more complex elements. … The logical structure of the verbal group realises the system of tense. … The primary tense is that functioning as Head, shown as α. This is the Deictic tense: past, present or future relative to the speech event. The modifying elements, at β and beyond, are secondary tenses; they express past, present or future relative to the time selected in the previous tense. Realisations are shown in Table 6-12.

Friday 25 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of A Modalised Passive Verbal Group

 Matthiessen (1995: 730):

Examples: 
positive & finite: temporal: future & unmarked focus & secondary: past: secondary: future: secondary: past & passive


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this misconstrues and misrepresents the univariate structure of the verbal group. Because there are only five features selected — modal, past, future, past, passive — there are only five elements of univariate structure, not six:

should have been going to have been tested

α modal      β past        γ future        δ past     ε passive

Wednesday 23 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of Modalised Past Tense

 Matthiessen (1995: 730):

Examples:
positive & finite: modal & unmarked focus & secondary: past & active


Blogger Comments:

This misconstrues and misrepresents the univariate structure of the verbal group. Because there are only two features selected, modal and past, there are only two elements of univariate structure: the expression of modality and the secondary past tense have + V-en: (with the -en not realised phonologically or graphologically for this irregular verb):

should have become

α modal  β past

Monday 21 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of Modalised Verbal Groups

 Matthiessen (1995: 730):

Examples:
positive & finite: modal & unmarked focus & no secondary & active

 

Blogger Comments:

This misconstrues and misrepresents the univariate structure of these verbal groups. Because there is no secondary tense, there is only one element of univariate structure: the expression of modality:

would live

can see

α modal

Saturday 19 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of The Marked Simple Past Tense

 Matthiessen (1995: 730):

Examples:
positive & finite: temporal: past & marked focus : polarity (not shown in network) & no secondary & active

 

Blogger Comments:

This miconstrues and misrepresents the univariate structure of this verbal group. To be clear, the tense of this verbal group is again the simple past (V-ed), and so there is only one structural realisation of tense, not two:

did fall

α past

Thursday 17 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of The Unmarked Simple Past Tense

Matthiessen (1995: 730):
Examples:

positive & finite: temporal: past & unmarked focus & no secondary & active

 

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the tense of this verbal group is the simple past, realised structurally by V-ed, which is realised phonologically and graphologically by vowel change in this irregular verb:

fell

α past

Tuesday 15 August 2023

The Univariate Structure Of The Verbal Group

Matthiessen (1995: 715):

The verbal group is a group of verbs - one lexical verb and one or more auxiliaries. It is organised both univariately and multivariately. The principles will be discussed below; the univariate structure is a simple hypotactic one, realised progressively — α –> β –> γ –> δ (as in α must β have γ been going δ to leave) and so on.


Blogger Comments:

[1] This is misleading. The elements of the univariate structure of the verbal group are not words. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 398-9):

… the elements of the logical structure are not the individual words but certain rather more complex elements. … The logical structure of the verbal group realises the system of tense. … The primary tense is that functioning as Head, shown as α. This is the Deictic tense: past, present or future relative to the speech event. The modifying elements, at β and beyond, are secondary tenses; they express past, present or future relative to the time selected in the previous tense. Realisations are shown in Table 6-12.

And so, importantly, the Event does not figure as an element in the univariate structure. Halliday (1985: 184n):

A major point of difference between the verbal group and the nominal group is that the Event (unlike the Thing) is not the point of departure for the recursive modifying relationship. Hence it does not figure as an element in the notation.

[2] To be clear, this misrepresents the univariate structure of the verbal group. Only three features, not four, are selected in this verbal group: modal, past and future, realised as:

[must] [have + V-en] [be going to + V]

must have been going to leave

α modal     β past      γ future

Sunday 13 August 2023

Non-Identifiable Determination

Matthiessen (1995: 700):
Now let us turn to non-identifiable determination. The interpretation given in IFG Section 6.2.1 will be used and elaborated on. Non-identifiable determination is not concerned with how to identify an already established instantiation but with how a class is instantiated — whether it is instantiated completely or only partially, whether it is instantiated selectively or not, and so on. The general distinctions are the same for both singular instantiations and non-singular (i.e., mass or plural) instantiations.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this again confuses a genuine nominal group system, DETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 366) with the 'identifiability' of the non-structural cohesive system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

Friday 11 August 2023

The Systems Of Determination And Postdetermination

Matthiessen (1995: 698):
The most general system in the DETERMINATION region of systems is concerned with the general recoverability or identifiability status of the discourse referent being presented — is it recoverable or not? If it is, then the issue is how it is to be recovered (as an instance of some general class); if it is not, then the issue is how it is to be presented (as an instance of some general class). (In either case, the system of POSTDETERMINATION may give some further indication of the status of the referents as instances of the general class: the usual three trouble-makers; these famous two stars; the alleged two burglars.)


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, this again confuses a genuine nominal group system, DETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 366) with the 'identifiability' of the non-structural cohesive system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

[2] To be clear, this confuses a genuine nominal group system, POSTDETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 373) with the 'identifiability' of the non-structural cohesive system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

Non-structural cohesive systems are not systems of the nominal group, since systems of the nominal group specify the structure of the nominal group, relationships between its elements, whereas systems of COHESION do not.

Wednesday 9 August 2023

The System Of Determination [2]

Matthiessen (1995: 698):
Like THEMATISATION, DETERMINATION depends on a dynamic model of the environment in which the text is unfolding, in particular of the current state of development from the point of view of the addressee. In this dynamic text model, it has to be possible to determine whether a given referent is identifiable or not to the addressee. (Non-identifiable determiners in particular overlap in coverage with the quantifiers of formal logic, but the distinctions are not the same.)


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this again confuses a genuine nominal group system, DETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 366) with the 'identifiability' of the non-structural cohesive system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

Non-structural cohesive systems are not systems of the nominal group, since systems of the nominal group specify the structure of the nominal group, relationships between its elements, whereas systems of COHESION do not.

Monday 7 August 2023

The System Of Determination [1]

Matthiessen (1995: 695):
In the clause, THEMATISATION determines the thematic status of participants and circumstances (thematic vs. rhematic). In the information unit in spoken English, INFORMATION determines their information status (given vs. new). These textual statuses are independent of, but clearly related to, a third textual status, the identifiability status of referents; this status is controlled by DETERMINATION in the nominal group.

In the experiential perspective, an object is a general class, possibly with subcategorisations and descriptive attributes. The textual perspective is concerned with the instantiation of the class; with the object as a referent. In the case of objects, both perspectives are integrated in the nominal group. DETERMINATION is the resource for determining whether a referent is identifiable or not; and if it is, how it is to be identified; and if it is not, how it is to be selected as an instance of a class. DETERMINATION is concerned with things as instances, not as experiential classes.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this again confuses a genuine nominal group system, DETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 366) with the 'identifiability' of the non-structural cohesive system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

Non-structural cohesive systems are not systems of the nominal group, since systems of the nominal group specify the structure of the nominal group, relationships between its elements, whereas systems of COHESION do not.

Saturday 5 August 2023

The Systems Of Determination And Substitution/Ellipsis

Matthiessen (1995: 693):
From a textual point of view, the nominal group provides the resources for presenting and contextualising discourse referents — instances of participants brought into referential space — and for differentiating between continuous and contrastive information. There are two textual sets of systems, DETERMINATION and SUBSTITUTION/ELLIPSIS. Both deal with recoverability of information. DETERMINATION is concerned with the recoverability status of discourse referents (their identifiability), whereas SUBSTITUTION/ELLIPSIS is concerned with the recoverability of words.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, these are non-structural cohesive systems, not systems of the nominal group. Systems of the nominal group specify the structure of the nominal group, relationships between its elements, whereas systems of COHESION do not.

[2] To be clear, this confuses a genuine nominal group system, DETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 366) with the non-structural cohesive system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

Thursday 3 August 2023

Intensified Classifiers

Matthiessen (1995: 664-5):
The adjectives that regularly serve as Classifiers - adjectives of provenance (Chinese, Burmese, Australian), of material (wooden, metallic, plastic), for example - are closer to the domain of nouns on the scale from prototypical adjectives to prototypical nouns. For instance, they are not scalar and intensifiable but form n-nary taxonomic oppositions (instead of binary scalar oppositions such as tall - short ). Thus we would not expect to get very metamorphic rocks. ¹²⁹

¹²⁹ But we do find examples such as a thoroughly modern woman, a very post-modern discourse, a very French attitude; more French than the French. Here the intensification seems to be concerned either with degree of (proto)typicality rather than value on a single scale or with some particular aspect that is characteristic of the quality.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the fact that intensification is possible in such instances suggests that the words are serving as Epithets, rather than Classifiers. Moreover, they can be seen to serve as interpersonal Epithets, since they express the speaker's attitude toward the Thing in question (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 376).

Tuesday 1 August 2023

The Nominal Group Deictic

Matthiessen (1995: 663):
Deictic, Postdeictic and Numerative are concerned with various aspects of the selection of instantial representatives of the general experiential category construed by the nominal group - whether they are recoverable/ identifiable to the addressee or not, how they are selected (as typical, usual, possible, etc. representatives), how many are selected, and so on.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this confuses the function of the Deictic as an element of nominal group structure, realising the system of DETERMINATION (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 365), with its non-structural cohesive function (recoverability, identifiability), realising the system of REFERENCE (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 623).

Sunday 30 July 2023

Logical Modification In The Nominal Group

Matthiessen (1995: 661, 663):



Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the Postmodifier is no longer included in the dependency notation. Halliday & Matthiessen (2004: 332n):
In previous editions the Postmodifier also was brought into the scope of the logical representation. But this appears to complicate the description without adding further to its explanatory power.

Friday 28 July 2023

The Symbolisation Subtype Of Facet

Matthiessen (1995: 657):
With elaborating selection, the Facet construes the order of abstraction (picture, symbol, etc.) or delicacy (type, example, etc.) of the participant being represented whereas with extending selection, the Facet construes the size (collection, cup, part, etc.). The more delicate types are set out in Table 7-10 below together with nouns that can serve as the Head of the nominal group realising Facet.


Blogger Comments:

As previously explained, the symbolisation category does not satisfy the requirements of a Facet, because the Head always conflates with Thing in such nominal groups. That is, words like picture, photograph, painting, drawing, sketch, symbol, sign always function as Thingnot Facet — because such words serve as the participant in the transitivity structure of the clause. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 394):

… the Thing is the entity that is functioning as participant in the transitivity structure of the clause … .

Wednesday 26 July 2023

A Thematic Test For Head/Thing Conflation

Matthiessen (1995: 657):
The more weight the nominal group with the potential for serving as Facet is given, in particular through specific determination, the less likely it is to be interpreted as Facet and the more likely its Head is to be interpreted as the Thing of the whole nominal group, as in I haven't seen this beautiful expensive picture of Dorian Grey before. Here the Postmodifier is unlikely to serve as Theme — that is, we would hardly get Dorian Grey I haven't seen this beautiful expensive picture of before; and this indicates that the multivariate and univariate structures are congruent with picture as Head/ Thing.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the thematic potential of the Postmodifier is irrelevant to whether Head and Thing are conflated. The Thing is the experiential element of the nominal group that serves as the participant in the experiential structure of the clause. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 394):

What all these have in common is that, while the Thing is the entity that is functioning as participant in the transitivity structure of the clause … . It is the Head that determines the value of the entity in the mood system, and therefore as a potential Subject.

In this instance, picture serves as Thing because it is this that I haven't seen, not Dorian Grey

Monday 24 July 2023

"Facet" Nominal Group

Matthiessen (1995: 656):



Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the Thing is the entity that functions as participant in the transitivity structure of the clause. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 394):
What all these have in common is that, while the Thing is the entity that is functioning as participant in the transitivity structure of the clause, the logical Head of the construction is something that constrains the entity in terms of the two variables mentioned above. It is the Head that determines the value of the entity in the mood system, and therefore as a potential Subject.

On this basis, the Thing in this nominal group is picture, as demonstrated by the clause

a picture of Dorian Grey was thrown in the bin

where it is clearly a picture that was thrown in the bin, not Dorian Grey. Thus:

Saturday 22 July 2023

Multivariate Structure Of The Nominal Group

Matthiessen (1995: 652):



Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the Thing is the entity that functions as participant in the transitivity structure of the clause. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 394):
What all these have in common is that, while the Thing is the entity that is functioning as participant in the transitivity structure of the clause, the logical Head of the construction is something that constrains the entity in terms of the two variables mentioned above. It is the Head that determines the value of the entity in the mood system, and therefore as a potential Subject.

On this basis, the Thing in this nominal group is picture, as demonstrated by the clause

a picture of these famous first two marvellous brick houses with gardens was thrown in the bin

where it is clearly a picture that was thrown in the bin, not houses. Thus:

Thursday 20 July 2023

The Logical Structure Of The Verbal Group

Matthiessen (1995: 640-1):
In contrast, in verbal groups, the Head is not the main experiential function, the Event, but rather the Finite, i.e., the function that relates to the now of the communicative exchange — the interpersonal reference point created in the speech interaction. Consequently, expansion within the verbal group of the Head does not start as a construal of the event; rather, it construes a (stepwise) move away from the interpersonal reference point of the Finite to the experiential Event through time and/or modality.

Blogger Comments:

[1] Again, this misrepresents Halliday's analysis of the logical structure of the verbal group. As previously explained, the logical structure realises the system of TENSE, so the elements of logical structure are realisations of tense, not individual words. The Head is not the Finite, but the realisation of primary tense. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 398-9):
However, the structural labelling of the words that make up the verbal group is of limited value, not only because the meaning can be fully represented in terms of grammatical features (of tense, voice, polarity and modality), but also because it is the logical structure that embodies the single most important semantic feature of the English verb, its recursive tense system, and the elements of the logical structure are not the individual words but certain rather more complex elements. …
The logical structure of the verbal group realises the system of tense. … Thus tense in English is a recursive system. The primary tense is that functioning as Head, shown as α. This is the Deictic tense: past, present or future relative to the speech event. The modifying elements, at β and beyond, are secondary tenses; they express past, present or future relative to the time selected in the previous tense. Realisations are shown in Table 6-12.

[2] Again, this misrepresents Halliday's analysis of the logical structure of the verbal group. As previously explained, the Finite and the Event are not elements of logical structure, so the expansion of the verbal group can not be 'a stepwise move from the Finite to the Event'.

Tuesday 18 July 2023

The Logical Structure Of Groups

Matthiessen (1995: 640):

As the examples above show, the Head (⍺) of each type of group is a different multivariate function, viz. Thing (nominal group), Circumstance (adverbial group of ideational type), and Finite (verbal group).


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the Postmodifier of the nominal group (with balconies in Figure 7-5) is no longer analysed as a β element. Halliday & Matthiessen (2004: 332n):
In previous editions the Postmodifier also was brought into the scope of the logical representation. But this appears to complicate the description without adding further to its explanatory power.

However, more importantly, here Matthiessen seriously misrepresents the the logical structure of the verbal group. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 398-9):

… the elements of the logical structure are not the individual words but certain rather more complex elements. … The logical structure of the verbal group realises the system of tense. … The primary tense is that functioning as Head, shown as α. This is the Deictic tense: past, present or future relative to the speech event. The modifying elements, at β and beyond, are secondary tenses; they express past, present or future relative to the time selected in the previous tense. Realisations are shown in Table 6-12.

As can be seen, the elements of logical structure of the verbal group are not words, and it is the realisation of primary tense, not the word serving as the Finite element, that functions as the Head (⍺) of the verbal group. Halliday (1985: 177):

Importantly, the Finite element realises not just primary tense, but also modality and polarity (Halliday 1985: 75), but it is only the realisation of primary tense that functions as the Head (⍺) of the verbal group.

Finally, the Event has never featured in the logical structure of the verbal group. Halliday (1985: 184n):

A major point of difference between the verbal group and the nominal group is that the Event (unlike the Thing) is not the point of departure for the recursive modifying relationship. Hence it does not figure as an element in the notation.

Sunday 16 July 2023

Group And Word Classes

Matthiessen (1995: 638):

Verbal groups are groups of verbs, nominal groups are groups of nominals, and adverbial groups are groups of adverbials.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, there are exceptions to this generalisation, such as verbs serving as Epithets and Classifiers in nominal groups, adverbs serving as Submodifiers in nominal groups, and adjectives (nominals) serving as the Event in verbal groups. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 427n):

Certain adjectives can serve as Event in a verbal group in a hypotactic verbal group complex, e.g. (conation: potentiality:) be able/apt/prone/likely → to do; (modulation: time: frequency:) be wont  to do; (modulation: manner: quality:) be wise/right/wrong  to do; (projection:) be willing/keen/eager  to do; be afraid/scared  to do.

Friday 14 July 2023

The Minor Theme Of A Prepositional Phrase

Matthiessen (1995: 637):

The textual option in the prepositional phrase has just been illustrated for wh-phrases. That is, the prepositional phrase may be thematic as a whole, or its Complement/Range may alternatively be thematic on its own:
What's it | like_ | out today?
That house I'll never set my foot | in_ | again.
From the point of view of the prepositional phrase, the Complement/ Range conflates with a function that is external to the prepositional phrase (shown as Theme ↑). If the nominal group serving as Complement/ Range has an elaborating or extending Facet (Selector) and its structure is ambivalent, it is even possible to thematise only the non-Facet part of the nominal group (cf. Matthiessen, 1991):
That peak I've never talked about [a picture of _].


Blogger Comments:

[1] Again, this misconstrues what is thematic at clause rank — the prepositional phrase or its Complement/Range — as thematic at phrase rank.

[2] To be clear, the clause That peak I've never talked about a picture of is extremely unlikely.

Wednesday 12 July 2023

Minor Theme In Prepositional Phrases

Matthiessen (1995: 630):
As already noted above, prepositional phrases can be interpreted as mini-clauses (IFG, p. 180; 212-3). Experientially, they offer the system MINOR TRANSITIVITY — a system of relational process types; interpersonally, they offer MINOR MOOD, where the distinction is simply between wh- and non-wh-; and textually they offer MINOR THEME which is the choice between having an externally thematic participant or not. These systems are set out in Figure 7-3. (The symbol ↑ indicates that the Complement of the prepositional phrase is conflated with a function external to the domain of the prepositional phrase, viz. the Theme of the clause in which the prepositional phrase serves: See Section 7.1.2.3 below.)
This system network thus defines a three-dimensional paradigm; examples are given in Table 7-5.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, Halliday proposes no thematic structure for the prepositional phrase. Here Matthiessen misconstrues what is thematic at clause rank — the Range/Complement of prepositional phrase — as thematic at phrase rank. A structure is the relation between functions, so a thematic structure for a prepositional phrase would be a relation between the minor Process/Predicator and the minor Range/Complement.

[2] To be clear, neither the two examples of 'externally thematic projection' are likely instances of English:

  • who is it going to rain according to?
  • Henry it's going to rain according to

Monday 10 July 2023

The Minor Range Of A Prepositional Phrase

 Matthiessen (1995: 627):

As already noted, a prepositional phrase is like a mini-clause — more specifically, it is like a mini relational clause. For example, corresponding to the relational clause The fence surrounds the property, we have the prepositional phrase around the property. While the finite clause represents both participants entering into the relation (Token + Value, or Carrier+ Attribute), the phrase only represents one of them (the one construed in the clause as Value or Attribute).


Blogger Comments:


To be clear, since, for Halliday (1994: 151-2), a prepositional phrase is like a relational or verbal clause, the minor Range of a prepositional phrase may also correspond to the Verbiage or Sayer of a verbal clause — the former when the phrase serves as Matter, the latter when it serves as Angle.

Saturday 8 July 2023

Groups Of Words Of The Same Primary Class

Matthiessen (1995: 627):
To sum up, groups differ from phrases in that 
(i) they are groups of words of the same primary class (nominals, verbs, or adverbials), so their functional potential is related to the Head word;


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, there are exceptions to this generalisation, as when a verb serves as the Epithet or Classifier of a nominal group, or an adverb serves as Sub-Modifier; see Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 427).

Thursday 6 July 2023

Prepositional Phrases As Mini Relational Clauses

Matthiessen (1995: 626):

In contrast, prepositional phrases are mini-clauses, more specifically mini relational clauses — shrunken clauses (see IFG Ch. 6).

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, for Halliday (1994: 151-2), a prepositional phrase is like a relational or verbal clause:

For the present discussion, what is important is the notion of ‘circumstance’ as a kind of additional minor process, subsidiary to the main one, but embodying some of the features of a relational or verbal process, and so introducing a further entity as an indirect participant in the clause.

Tuesday 4 July 2023

Preposition Group As Word Complex

Matthiessen (1995: 626):
Note that adverbial group is treated quite broadly here; it includes conjunctions and continuatives as well as adverbs at Head. In IFG, adverbial groups and conjunction groups are distinguished. Here they are just taken as more delicate types of adverbial group. IFG also recognises a prepositional group. Here groups of prepositions are simply treated as complexes of prepositions at word rank (paratactic - e.g., extending: above —> and below the surface; enhancing: from —> beyond the mountains).


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this treatment has the advantage of acknowledging the hybrid nature of the prepositional phrase, with one element realised by a unit (complex) at word rank, and the other element realised by a unit (complex) at group rank, and also of economising the rank scale, since it proposes just a single class of form at group/phrase rank for the word class 'preposition'.

Sunday 2 July 2023

Verbs Of Behaviour

Matthiessen (1995: 348):
Certain verbs of behaviour (including verbal behaviour) are "reciprocal" and can serve either in clauses with a participant realised by a plural nominal group or coordinated nominal groups or with a circumstance of Accompaniment. For instance, fight can serve in either Anne and Henry fought or in Anne fought with Henry.

Similarly: chat, discuss, speak, talk, dance, fight, kiss, play, waltz. Outside the behavioural domain …


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, fight patterns like a material Process, not a behavioural Process, since it allows a co-participant to be construed as Goal in an effective clause:

Henry fought Anne

whereas a behavioural Process does not:

*Henry sneezed Anne

*Henry laughed Anne 

Friday 30 June 2023

Circumstances Not Catered For In IFG Typology

Matthiessen (1995: 344):

Certain examples of circumstances are not really catered for in the IFG typology presented above. They include For us, this is a boon; it was a sad day for most of us (but cf. Angle above).


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, on the IFG model, these are participants — Beneficiaries — not circumstances.

Wednesday 28 June 2023

The Direction Of Coding In SFL Theorising

Matthiessen (1995: 306):
Intensive clauses play an important role in linguistic theory because they allow us to construe various relationships that are fundamental in semiotic systems. For instance, identifying intensive clauses can construe realisation — the relationship between SIGNIFIED (Value) and SIGNIFIER (Token). See Figure 4-29 and note that the direction is from the signifier to the signified — the interpretive direction in linguistic theorising.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the direction from Token to Value is decoding (Halliday & Matthiessen 2014: 280) and this applies to theorising in which lower levels of abstraction, e.g. forms, are decoded by reference to higher levels of abstraction, e.g. meanings.

Theorising in SFL, however, proceeds in the opposite direction: higher levels of abstraction, e.g. meanings, are encoded by reference to lower levels of abstraction, e.g. forms. That is, in SFL Theory, the question is not 'what do these forms mean?' but 'how are these meanings expressed?'. Halliday (1985 & 1994: xiv):

Monday 26 June 2023

Circumstantial Relational Clauses

 Matthiessen (1995: 305):

The system RELATION TYPE is simultaneous with RELATIONAL ABSTRACTION. There are three terms — intensive/possessive/circumstantial. These three types are manifestations in the environment of relational processes of the highly generalised types of expansion that permeate the lexicogrammatical system: elaborating — intensive, extending — possessive, and enhancing — circumstantial.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the exception here is a circumstantial relational clause of matter — such as This story concerns a lost dog  — where the relation is one of projectionnot enhancement.

Saturday 24 June 2023

The Agency Of Identifying Clauses

Matthiessen (1995: 305):
Identifying clauses are interpreted as invariably effective here ⁵⁸
⁵⁸ This is a simplification: Identifying can also combine with middle — see Halliday (1967/8).


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, identifying clauses are only effective in agency if encoding or assigned. The least marked variant, unassigned decoding, is middle in agency.

Thursday 22 June 2023

Existential Clauses As Invariably Middle With Only One Participant

Matthiessen (1995: 300):

Existential clauses are treated as a subtype of relational clauses here. They are invariably middle. They are the limiting case, since there is only one participant, the Existent, and thus the process is no true relation — no true expansion linking two participants.


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this is inconsistent with Halliday & Matthiessen (1999: 157), where effective existential clauses with two participants are proposed:



Tuesday 20 June 2023

Existential vs Expanding Relational Clauses

Matthiessen (1995: 299):
Relational clauses are either EXISTENTIAL or EXPANDING. Existential clauses constitute the limiting case of being — a mode of being with only one participant, the Existent. In contrast, expanding clauses always involve a relation between two participants — they are true relational clauses in this respect. (A restricted exceptional subtype will be noted below where one of the two participants is fused with the Process.) They are called expanding relational clauses because the relation covers the same semantic space as expansion elsewhere in the grammar, e.g., in the clause complex and in conjunction.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, Halliday ± Matthiessen (1985, 1994, 2004, 2014) distinguish existential clauses from relational clauses.

[2] To be clear, the exception here is a circumstantial relational clause of matter — such as This story concerns a lost dog  — where the relation is one of projection, not expansion.

Sunday 18 June 2023

Processes Of Verbal Impact

Matthiessen (1995: 285):
Processes of verbal impact are also on the borderline between the verbal domain and the material domain. Like verbal processes, they have a Sayer, which can be a speaker as well as some other symbol source; but the participant addressed is not construed as a Beneficiary that may be marked by to, but rather as a Goal-like Target of verbal impact. Verbs occurring in this type of clause include:
accuse, blame, congratulate, criticise.praise, rebuke


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the 'Goal-like' Target (Medium) of such verbal clauses demonstrates that they are effective, not middle, in agency, contrary to Matthiessen (1995: 283).

Friday 16 June 2023

Processes of Verbal Behaviour

Matthiessen (1995: 284):

Processes of verbal behaviour are on the borderline between verbal and behavioural; they can alternatively be interpreted as behavioural processes. They include:

speak, talk, argue, converse, confer, chat, chatter, gossip, yak


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, Halliday ± Matthiessen (1985, 1994, 2004, 2014) interpret these as behavioural, not verbal.

Wednesday 14 June 2023

Verbal Clauses As Middle Only

Matthiessen (1995: 283):
Table 4-30: Characteristic Properties of Verbal Clauses

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, this is inconsistent with Halliday (1994: 165-6), where targeted verbal clauses are interpreted as effective:


Monday 12 June 2023

Process + Medium Collocations In Behavioural Clauses

Matthiessen (1995: 253):
Process + Medium. There is a set of features of material process type in the context of which we find Process + Medium pairs. These general features include 
  • change in quantity (fall + temperature), 
  • change in quality, 
    • growth & improvement (repair + [mechanical device such as] car, heal + wound, ripen + fruit, mature + child, age + wine) or
    • deterioration (decay + teeth, rot + meat, wilt + flower), 
  • phase: beginning (break out + war), 
  • preparation for use (make + bed, lay + table, prime + gun, pump); 
  • behaviour: typical sound (neigh + horse, bark + dog), 
  • behaviour: typical movement (waddle + duck, trot + horse, canter + horse, flap + wing, crawl + snake), 
  • behaviour: ingesting (breathe + air, inhale + smoke, drink + liquid, take + medicine).

Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, since the Medium of a behavioural clause is a Behaver, interpreting the collocation flap + wing construes wing as conscious. The fact that such a collocation occurs in effective material clauses is demonstrated by the agnate clause the young albatross flapped its wings where wings can only be interpreted as the Goal of a material Process.

[2] To be clear, none of these collocations occurs in behavioural clauses, because none of the Mediums — air, smoke, liquid, medicine — is a Behaver (the Medium of a behavioural Process). Moreover, clauses with such collocations are effective, and so the interpretation of such clauses as behavioural is inconsistent with Matthiessen (1995: 211):
If MATERIALMENTAL, and RELATIONAL are taken as major types, as they are in IFG, it is interesting to note that the other minor types, BEHAVIOURALVERBAL and EXISTENTIAL are all more restricted in AGENCY - they are middle only. 

Saturday 10 June 2023

Interactive (Reciprocal) Behavioural Processes [2]

Matthiessen (1995: 252-3):
Some verbs are less likely with the circumstantial option — for example Anne hugged with Henry is unlikely - and the potential coparticipant is construed alternatively as a Goal instead — hug, embrace, kiss, marry, divorce:
Anne and Henry hugged/embraced/kissed/married/divorced:

Anne hugged/embraced/kissed/married/divorced Henry


Blogger Comments:

Again, the fact that a co-participant is construed as a Goal is evidence that the Process is effective material, not middle behavioural.

Again, the interpretation of effective clauses as behavioural is inconsistent with Matthiessen (1995: 211):
If MATERIALMENTAL, and RELATIONAL are taken as major types, as they are in IFG, it is interesting to note that the other minor types, BEHAVIOURALVERBAL and EXISTENTIAL are all more restricted in AGENCY - they are middle only.

Thursday 8 June 2023

Interactive (Reciprocal) Behavioural Processes [1]

Matthiessen (1995: 252):
Interactive (reciprocal) behavioural material processes have the special property that coparticipation can be construed either as one participant which is internally complex (e.g., Henry and Anne), in which case a reciprocal pronoun as Accompaniment may be added (e.g., Henry and Anne ... with each other), or as one participant configured with a circumstance of Accompaniment (e.g., Henry ... with Anne), as in 
Henry and Anne danced/fought/chatted :
Henry and Anne danced/fought/chatted with each other:
Henry danced/fought/chatted with Anne.

In other words, a participant may be extended paratactically or circumstantially; verbs serving in this type of clause include:
dance, waltz, chat, gossip, talk, converse, negotiate, discuss, argue, sing, collaborate, meet, play, fight, box


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, fought patterns here like an effective material Process, not a middle behavioural ('material') Process, since it allows a co-participant to be construed as Goal:

Henry fought Anne

whereas a behavioural Process does not:

*Henry danced Anne

*Henry chatted Anne 

The same holds true for meet and box:

Henry met Anne

Henry boxed Anne


Moreover, the interpretation of effective clauses as behavioural is inconsistent with Matthiessen (1995: 211):
If MATERIALMENTAL, and RELATIONAL are taken as major types, as they are in IFG, it is interesting to note that the other minor types, BEHAVIOURALVERBAL and EXISTENTIAL are all more restricted in AGENCY - they are middle only. 

Tuesday 6 June 2023

Behavioural Processes With Reflexive Pronouns

Matthiessen (1995: 252):

(1) Certain behavioural processes that are confined to the self may occur with or without a reflexive pronoun; these include processes of grooming — behave (oneself), clean (oneself), comb (oneself), [un]dress (oneself), hide (oneself), prepare (oneself) for, shave (oneself), stretch (oneself), wash (oneself):

 

Blogger Comments:

To be clear, the possibility of a reflexive pronoun in such clauses rules out these verbs as serving as behavioural Processes, because, if the pronoun is interpreted as the Range of the Process, it is not a Behaviour, as it must be for behavioural clauses, and if it is interpreted as the Medium of the Process it is not a Behaver, as it must be for behavioural clauses.

Cf this impossibility for genuine behaviourals: *stare oneself, *grumble oneself, *frown oneself, *sneeze oneself, *stand oneself

Note that instances like he laughed himself sick are material clauses, as demonstrated by the inclusion of the resultative Attribute sick.

Sunday 4 June 2023

Behavioural Processes And Projection

Matthiessen (1995: 251-2):
Behavioural processes can tentatively be divided into intro-active and inter-active ones. Intro-active processes cover active equivalents of inert sensing (realised by mental clauses) — perception, cognition, and affect — and a few others. Some of these may quote. Interactive behaviour may involve extension - within the Behaver (x and y danced) or as a separate circumstance of Accompaniment (x danced with y )'., See Table 4-19.
As noted earlier, in IFG Section 5.5.1 (pp. 138-40), behavioural processes are separate from material ones; in the current grammar, they are treated as a subtype of material processes. In some earlier treatments, such as Halliday (1976: Ch. 11), those behavioural processes concerned with mental processing as an activity (smiling, laughing, listening, looking, watching, pondering, etc.) were treated as a type of mental process. The different treatments reflect the fact that behavioural processes, in some respects, fall between material processes and mental ones. For instance, like mental processes their Medium is normally conscious; but unlike mental processes (as a class) they cannot project or have a metaphenomenal Range (Phenomenon). (They can, however, have a macrophenomenal Range: Little Bobby's parents watched him recite Ode to a Grecian Urn with tears in their eyes.)


Blogger Comments:

To be clear, for Halliday, behavioural processes cannot project, and when such verbs serve in a quoting nexus, they add a behavioural feature to verbal Process. Halliday (1994: 139):